Showing posts with label felsefe. Show all posts
Showing posts with label felsefe. Show all posts

Tuesday, June 21, 2022

Russell and mathematical certainty

 


 “I wanted certainty in the kind of way in which people want religious faith. I thought that certainty is more likely to be found in mathematics than elsewhere. But I discovered that many mathematical demonstrations, which my teachers expected me to accept, were full of fallacies, and that, if certainty were indeed discoverable in mathematics, it would be in a new field of mathematics, with more solid foundations than those that had hitherto been thought secure. But as the work proceeded, I was continually reminded of the fable about the elephant and the tortoise. Having constructed an elephant upon which the mathematical world could rest, I found the elephant tottering, and proceeded to construct a tortoise to keep the elephant from falling. But the tortoise was no more secure then the elephant, and after some twenty years of very arduous toil, I came to the conclusion that there was nothing more that I could do in the way of making mathematical knowledge indubitable.”


“Mathematics is, I believe,” says Russell, “the chief source of the belief in eternal and exact truth, as well as in a super-sensible intelligible world. Geometry deals with exact circles, but no sensible object is exactly circular; however carefully we may use our compasses, there will be some imperfections and irregularities. This suggests the view that all exact reasoning applies to ideal as opposed to sensible objects; it is natural to go further, and to argue that thought is nobler than sense, and the objects of thought more real than those of sense-perception. Mystical doctrines as to the relation of time to eternity are also reinforced by pure mathematics, for mathematical objects, such as number, if real at all, are eternal and not in time. Such eternal objects can be conceived as God’s thoughts. Hence Plato’s doctrine that God is a geometer, and Sir James Jeans’ belief that He is addicted to arithmetic. Rationalistic as opposed to apocalyptic religion has been, ever since Pythagoras, and notably ever since Plato, very completely dominated by mathematics and mathematical method.

Friday, March 4, 2022

Descartes

 


D’Alembert wrote that it was Descartes who first “dared . . . to show intelligent minds how to throw off the yoke of scholasticism, of opinion, of authority—in a word, of prejudices and barbarism. . . . He can be thought of as a leader of conspirators who, before anyone else, had the courage to arise against a despotic and arbitrary power, and who, in preparing a resounding revolution, laid the foundations of a more just and happier government which he himself was not able to see established.” 

Philosophers of the scholastic persuasion pointed to the dangerous parallel between Descartes’s scientific individualism and the outlawed Protestant heresy. Descartes said individual thinkers could find scientific truth; Protestants said individual souls could find direct communion with the Almighty. But the Holy Roman Catholic Church knew that individual souls and thinkers could be deceived. It took the experience and wisdom of the Church to prevent the seeker from wandering astray. Despite such scholastic criticism, Descartes quickly came to dominate West European intellectual life.

**

Like Galileo, Descartes recognized mathematics as the principal tool for revealing truths of nature. He was more explicit than Galileo about how to do it. In every scientific problem, said Descartes, find an algebraic equation relating an unknown variable to a known one. Then solve the algebraic equation! With the development of calculus, Descartes’s doctrine was essentially justified. Today we don’t say “find an algebraic equation.” We say “construct a mathematical model.” This is only a technical generalization of Descartes’s idea. Our scientific technology is an inheritance from Descartes.


 

Pythagoreans!

 


The number one, they argued, is the generator of numbers and the number of reason; the number two is the first even or female number, the number of opinion; three is the first true male number, the number of harmony, being composed of unity and diversity; four is the number of justice or retribution, indicating the squaring of accounts; five is the number of marriage, the union of the first true male and female numbers; and six is the number of creation. Each number had its peculiar attributes. The holiest of all was the number ten, or the tetractys, for it represented the number of the universe, including the sum of all possible dimensions. [See also Heath, 1981, p. 75.] A single point is the generator of dimensions, two points determine a line of dimension one, three points S (not on a line) determine a triangle with area of dimension two, and four points (not in a plane) determine a tetrahedron with volume of dimension three; the sum of the numbers representing all dimensions, therefore, is . . . ten. It is a tribute to the abstraction of Pythagorean mathematics that the veneration of the number ten evidently was not dictated by anatomy of the human hand or foot.”

Friday, January 28, 2022

Philosophy of mathematics

 

                                                                                                       https://www.durham.ac.uk/departments/academic/mathematical-sciences/

Philosophy of mathematics should be tested against five kinds of mathematical practice: research, application, teaching, history, computing.

**

The need to check philosophy of mathematics against mathematical research doesn’t require explication. Many important philosophers of mathematics were mathematical researchers: Pascal, Descartes, Leibniz, d’Alembert, Hilbert, Brouwer, Poincaré, Rényi, and Bishop come to mind. Applied mathematics isn’t illegitimate or marginal. Advances in mathematics for science and technology often are inseparable from advances in pure mathematics. Examples: Newton on universal gravitation and the infinitesimal calculus; Gauss on electromagnetism, astronomy, and geodesy (the last inspired that beautiful pure subject—differential geometry); Poincare on celestial mechanics; and von Neumann on quantum mechanics, fluid dynamics, computer design, numerical analysis, and nuclear explosions.

**

G. H. Hardy “famously” boasted: “I have never done anything ‘useful’. No discovery of mine has made, or is likely to make, directly or indirectly, for good or ill, the least difference to the amenity of the world.” Nevertheless, the Hardy-Weinberg law of genetics is better known than his profound contributions to analytic number theory. What’s worse, cryptology is making number theory applicable. Hardy’s contribution to that pure field may yet be useful. Twenty years after the war, mathematical purism was revived, influenced by the famous French group “Bourbaki.” That period is over. Today it’s difficult to find a mathematician who’ll say an unkind word about applied math.

**

On the basis of this reduction, philosophers of mathematics generally limit their attention to set theory, logic, and arithmetic. What does this assumption, that all mathematics is fundamentally set theory, do to Euclid, Archimedes, Newton, Leibniz, and Euler? No one dares to say they were thinking in terms of sets, hundreds of years before the set-theoretic reduction was invented. The only way out (implicit, never explicit) is that their own understanding of what they did must be ignored! We know better than they how to explicate their work! That claim obscures history, and obscures the present, which is rooted in history.

An adequate philosophy of mathematics must be compatible with the history of mathematics. It should be capable of shedding light on that history. Why did the Greeks fail to develop mechanics, along the lines that they developed geometry? Why did mathematics lapse in Italy after Galileo, to leap ahead in England, France, and Germany? Why was non-Euclidean geometry not conceived until the nineteenth century, and then independently rediscovered three times? The philosopher of mathematics who is historically conscious can offer such questions to the historian. But if his philosophy makes these questions invisible, then instead of stimulating the history of mathematics, he stultifies it. Computing is a major part of mathematical practice. The use of computing machines in mathematical proof is controversial. An adequate philosophy of mathematics should shed some light on this controversy.

 

Monday, December 27, 2021

Mathematical Objects

 


What’s the nature of mathematical objects?

The question is made difficult by a centuries-old assumption of Western philosophy: “There are two kinds of things in the world. What isn’t physical is mental; what isn’t mental is physical.”

Mental is individual consciousness. It includes private thoughts—mathematical and philosophical, for example—before they’re communicated to the world and become social—and also perception, fear, desire, despair, hope, and so on.

Physical is taking up space—having weight or energy. It’s flesh and bones, sound waves, X-rays, galaxies.

Frege showed that mathematical objects are neither physical nor mental. He labeled them “abstract objects.” What did he tell us about abstract objects? Only this: They’re neither physical nor mental.

Are there other things besides numbers that aren’t mental or physical?

Yes! Sonatas. Prices. Eviction notices. Declarations of war.

Not mental or physical, but not abstract either!

The U.S. Supreme Court exists. It can condemn you to death!

Is the Court physical? If the Court building were blown up and the justices moved to the Pentagon, the Court would go on. Is it mental? If all nine justices expired in a suicide cult, they’d be replaced.

The Court would go on. The Court isn’t the stones of its building, nor is it anyone’s minds and bodies. Physical and mental embodiment are necessary to it, but they’re not it. It’s a social institution. Mental and physical categories are insufficient to understand it. It’s comprehensible only in the context of American society.

**

Mathematics consists of concepts. Not pencil or chalk marks, not physical triangles or physical sets, but concepts, which may be suggested or represented by physical objects.

**

In reviewing The Mathematical Experience, the mathematical expositor and journalist Martin Gardner made this objection: When two dinosaurs wandered to the water hole in the Jurassic era and met another pair of dinosaurs happily sloshing, there were four dinosaurs at the water hole, even though no human was present to think, “2 + 2 = 4.” This shows, says Gardner, that 2+ 2 really is 4 in reality, not just in some cultural consciousness. 2 + 2 = 4 is a law of nature, he says, independent of human thought.

To untangle this knot, we must see that “2” plays two linguistic roles. Sometimes it’s an adjective; sometimes it’s a noun.

In “two dinosaurs,” “two” is a collective adjective. “Two dinosaurs plus two dinosaurs equals four dinosaurs” is telling about dinosaurs. If I say “Two discrete, reasonably permanent, non-interacting objects collected with two others makes four such objects,” I’m telling part of what’s meant by discrete, reasonably permanent non-interacting objects. That is a statement in elementary physics.

John Stuart Mill pointed out that with regard to discrete, reasonably permanent non-interacting objects, experience tells us

2 + 2 = 4.

In contrast, “Two is prime but four is composite” is a statement about the pure numbers of elementary arithmetic. Now “two” and “four” are nouns, not adjectives. They stand for pure numbers, which are concepts and objects. They are conceptual objects, shared by everyone who knows elementary arithmetic, described by familiar axioms and theorems.


The collective adjectives or “counting numbers” are finite. There’s a limit to how high anyone will ever count. Yet there isn’t any last counting number. If you counted up to, say, a billion, then you could count to a billion and one. In pure arithmetic, these two properties—finiteness, and not having a last—are contradictory. This shows that the counting numbers aren’t the pure numbers.

Consider the pure number 10^(1010). We easily ascertain some of its properties, such as: “The only prime factors of 10^(1010) are 2 and 5.” But we can’t count that high. In that sense, there’s no counting number equal to 10^(1010).

Körner made the same distinction, using uppercase for Counting Numbers (adjectives) and lowercase for “pure” natural numbers (nouns). Jacob Klein wrote that a related distinction was made by the Greeks, using their words “arithmos” and “logistiké.”

So “two” and “four” have double meanings: as Counting Numbers or as pure numbers. The formula
 

2 + 2 = 4
 

has a double meaning. It’s about counting—about how discrete, reasonably permanent, non-interacting objects behave. And it’s a theorem in pure arithmetic (Peano arithmetic if you like). This linguistic ambiguity blurs the difference between Counting Numbers and pure natural numbers. But it’s convenient. It’s comparable to the ambiguity of non-mathematical words, such as “art” or “America.”

The pure numbers rise out of the Counting Numbers. In a process related to Aristotle’s abstraction, they disconnect from “real” objects, to exist as shared concepts in the mind/brains of people who know elementary arithmetic. In that realm of shared concepts, 2 + 2 = 4 is a different fact, with a different meaning. And we can now show that it follows logically from other shared concepts, which we usually call axioms.

**

Once created and communicated, mathematical objects are there. They detach from their originator and become part of human culture. We learn of them as external objects, with known properties and unknown properties. Of the unknown properties, there are some we are able to discover.

**

Why do these objects, our own creations, so often become useful in describing nature? To answer this in detail is a major task for the history of mathematics, and for a psychology of mathematical cognition that may be coming to birth in Piaget and Vygotsky. To answer it in general, however, is easy. Mathematics is part of human culture and history, which are rooted in our biological nature and our physical and biological surroundings. Our mathematical ideas in general match our world for the same reason that our lungs match earth’s atmosphere.

**

Psychological and historical studies won’t make mathematical truth indubitable. But why expect mathematical truth to be indubitable? Correcting errors by confronting them with experience is the essence of science. What’s needed is explication of what mathematicians do—as part of general human culture, as well as in mathematical terms. The result will be a description of mathematics that mathematicians recognize—the kind of truth that’s obvious once said.  

Certain kinds of ideas (concepts, notions, conceptions, and so forth) have science-like quality. They have the rigidity, the reproducibility, of physical science. They yield reproducible results, independent of particular investigators. Such kinds of ideas are important enough to have a name. Study of the lawful, predictable parts of the physical world has a name: “physics.” 

Study of the lawful, predictable, parts of the social-conceptual world also has a name: “mathematics.” A world of ideas exists, created by human beings, existing in their shared consciousness. These ideas have objective properties, in the same sense that material objects have objective properties. The construction of proof and counterexample is the method of discovering the properties of these ideas. This branch of knowledge is called mathematics.

Saturday, December 25, 2021

Platonism vs Formalism

 

Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein

Two principal views of the nature of mathematics are prevalent among mathematicians—Platonism and formalism. Platonism is dominant, but it’s hard to talk about it in public. Formalism feels more respectable philosophically, but it’s almost impossible for a working mathematician to really believe it.

**

The formalist philosophy of mathematics is often condensed to a short slogan: “Mathematics is a meaningless game.” (“Meaningless” and “game” remain undefined. Wittgenstein showed that games have no strict definition, only a family resemblance.)

What do formalists mean by “game” when they call mathematics a game? Perhaps they use “game” to mean something “played by the rules.” (Now “play” and “rule” are undefined!)

For a game in that sense, two things are needed:
(2) people to play by the rules.
(1) rules.

Rule-making can be deliberate, as in Monopoly or Scrabble—or spontaneous, as in natural languages or elementary arithmetic.

In either case, the making of rules doesn’t follow rules!

Wittgenstein and some others seem to think that since the making of rules doesn’t follow rules, then the rules are arbitrary. They could just as well be any way at all. This is a gross error.

The rules of language and of mathematics are historically determined by the workings of society that evolve under pressure of the inner workings and interactions of social groups, and the physical and biological environment of earth.

**
In real life there are no totally rule-governed activities. Only more or less rule-governed ones, with more or less definite procedures for disputes. The rules and procedures evolve, sometimes formally like amending the U.S. Constitution, sometimes informally, as street games evolve with time and mixing of cultures. Is there totally unruly or ruleless behavior? Perhaps not. Mathematics is in part a rule-governed game. But one can’t overlook how the rules are made, how they evolve, and how disputes are resolved. That isn’t rule governed, and can’t be.

Computer proof is changing the way the game of mathematics is played. Wolfgang Haken thinks computer proof is permitted under the rules. Paul Halmos thinks it ought to be against the rules. Tom Tymoczko thinks it amounts to changing the rules. In the long run, what mathematicians publish, cite, and especially teach, will decide the rules. We have no French Academy to set rules, no cabal of team owners to say how to play our game. Our rules are set by our consensus, influenced and led by our most powerful or prestigious members (of course).

These considerations on games and rules in general show that one can’t understand mathematics (or any other nontrivial human activity) by simply finding rules that it follows or ought to follow. Even if that could be done, it would lead to more interesting questions: Why and whence those rules?

The notion of strictly following rules without any need for judgment is a fiction. It has its use and interest. It’s misleading to apply it literally to real life.

**

Platonism says mathematical objects are real and independent of our knowledge. Space-filling curves, uncountably infinite sets, infinite-dimensional manifolds—all the members of the mathematical zoo—are definite objects, with definite properties, known or unknown. These objects exist outside physical space and time. They were never created. They never change. By logic’s law of the excluded middle, a meaningful question about any of them has an answer, whether we know it or not. According to Platonism a mathematician is an empirical scientist, like a botanist. He can’t invent, because everything is already there. He can only discover.

**

The objections to Platonism are never answered: the strange parallel existence of two realities—physical and mathematical; and the impossibility of contact between the flesh-and-blood mathematician and the immaterial mathematical object. Platonism shares the fatal flaw of Cartesian dualism. To explain the existence and properties of mind and matter, Descartes postulated a different “substance” for each. But he couldn’t plausibly explain how the two substances interact, as mind and body do interact. In similar fashion, Platonists explain mathematics by a separate universe of abstract objects, independent of the material universe. But how do the abstract and material universes interact? How do flesh-and-blood mathematicians acquire the knowledge of number?

To answer, you have to forget Platonism, and look in the socio-cultural past and present, in the history of mathematics, including the tragic life of Georg Cantor.

The set-theoretic universe constructed by Cantor and generally adopted by Platonists is believed to include all mathematics, past, present, and future. In it, the uncountable set of real numbers is just the beginning of uncountable chains of uncountables. The cardinality of this set universe is unspeakably greater than that of the material world. It dwarfs the material universe to a tiny speck. And it was all there before there was an earth, a moon, or a sun, even before the Big Bang. Yet this tremendous reality is unnoticed! Humanity dreams on, totally unaware of it—except for us mathematicians. We alone notice it. But only since Cantor revealed it in 1890. Is this plausible? Is this credible? Roger Penrose declares himself a Platonist, but draws the line at swallowing the whole set-theoretic hierarchy.

Platonists don’t acknowledge the arguments against Platonism. They just reavow Platonism.

Frege’s point of view persists today among set-theoretic Platonists. It goes something like this:

1. Surely the empty set exists—we all have encountered it!
2. Starting from the empty set, perform a few natural operations, like forming the set of all subsets. Before long you have a magnificent structure in which you can embed the real numbers, complex numbers, quaternions, Hilbert spaces, infinite-dimensional differentiable manifolds, and anything else you like.
3. Therefore it’s vain to talk of inventing or creating mathematics. In this all-encompassing, set-theoretic structure, everything we could ever want or dream of is already present.

Yet most advances in mainstream mathematics are made without reference to any set-theoretic embedding. Saying Hilbert space was already there in the set universe is like telling Rodin, “The Thinker is a nice piece of work, but all you did was get rid of the extra marble. The statue was there inside the marble quarry before you were born.” Rodin made The Thinker by removing marble. Hilbert, von Neumann, and the rest made the theory of Hilbert space by analysing, generalizing, and rearranging mathematical ideas that were present in the mathematical atmosphere of their time.

(Reuben Hersh, What is mathematics really?)
**

“Mathematical objects are real. Their existence is an objective fact, independent of our knowledge of them. Infinite sets, uncountably infinite sets, infinite-dimensional manifolds, space-filling curves—all the denizens of the mathematical zoo—are definite objects, with definite properties. Some of their properties are known, some are unknown. These objects aren’t physical or material. They’re outside space and time. They’re immutable. They’re uncreated. A meaningful statement about one of these objects is true or false, whether we know it or not. Mathematicians are empirical scientists, like botanists. We can’t invent anything; it’s there already. We try to discover.”

**

Wednesday, May 1, 2019

Ene ve Zerre Risalesi



Benliğin bir yüzünü peygamberler silsilesi, diğer yüzünü ise felsefe tutmuştur.

• Peygamberlerin yolu olan yüzü hâlis kulluğun kaynağıdır. Yani benlik, kendini kul bilir, başkasına hizmet ettiğini anlar. Mahiyeti Yaratıcısına, Sahibine işaret eder. Yani başkasının mânâsını taşıdığını bilir. Varlığı başka bir varlığa tâbidir. Yani başka bir Zât’ın varlığıyla ayakta durduğuna ve O’nun yaratmasıyla sabit olduğuna inanır. Sahipliği farazidir. 

• Benliğin ikinci yüzünü ise felsefe tutmuştur. Felsefe, benliğe mânâ-yı ismiyle, yani sadece kendisini bildiren yönüyle bakar. Onun yalnız kendi kendine işaret ettiğini söyler. Mânâsı kendindedir, kendi hesabına çalışır, diye hükmeder. Benliğin varlığını aslî ve zâtına ait görür. Yani bizzat kendinden bir varlığı olduğunu kabul eder. Bir hayat hakkı bulunduğu, tasarrufu dairesindekilerin hakiki sahibi olduğu gibi temelsiz iddialar öne sürer. Varlığını sabit bir hakikat zanneder. Vazifesini, kendine hayranlığından doğan, zâtına ait bir mükemmelleşme çabası sayar. İşte felsefeciler yollarını bunun gibi pek çok çürük esas üzerine kurmuşlardır.

**

Felsefe silsilesinin en mükemmel fertleri ve dâhileri olan Platon, Aristoteles, İbni Sina ve Farabî gibi filozoflar, “İnsanın asıl gayesi ‘teşebbüh-ü bil-vâcib’dir, yani Vâcibü’l-Vücud’a benzemektir.” deyip firavunca bir hükme varmışlar. Benliği kamçılayıp şirk derelerinde serbestçe koşturarak sebeplere, putlara, tabiata ve yıldızlara tapmaya kadar varan türlü şirk yollarında gidenlere meydan vermişler. İnsanın özünde bulunan acz ve zaaf, fakr ve ihtiyaç, noksanlık ve kusur kapılarını kapayıp kulluğun yoluna set çekmişler. Tabiata saplanmış, şirkten tamamen çıkamamış, şükrün geniş kapısını bulamamışlar.

Peygamberler ve takipçileri ise insanın gayesi, vazifesi ilahî ahlâk ve yüksek seciyelerle ahlâklanmak, aczini bilip Cenâb-ı Hakk’ın kudretine sığınmak, zayıflığını görüp O’nun kuvvetine dayanmak, fakrını görüp rahmetine güvenmek, ihtiyacını görüp O’nun zenginliğinden yardım dilemek, kusurunu görüp af kapısını çalarak istiğfar etmek ve noksanlığını görüp O’nun kemâl vasıflarını tesbih etmektir, diye kulluğa yakışır bir hükme varmışlar.

İşte dini tanımayan felsefe böyle yolunu şaşırdığı için benlik kendi dizginini eline almış, dalâletin her türlüsüne koşmuş. Benliğin bu yüzünde bir zakkum ağacı büyüyüp insanlık âleminin yarısından fazlasını kaplamış.


**


Felsefe yolunun çürük esasları ile peygamber yolunun dosdoğru, sarsılmaz esaslarından doğan neticelerin binlerce kıyaslamasından, örnek olarak üç-dört tanesini göstereceğiz.

Mesela: Peygamberlerin rehberliğinde dinin, insanın şahsî hayatındaki neticelerinden olan “İlahî ahlâk ile ahlâklanıp Cenâb-ı Hakk’a, küçüklüğünüzün şuuru içinde yönelerek aczinizi, fakrınızı ve kusurunuzu biliniz, O’nun dergâhına kul olunuz.” düsturu nerede… Felsefenin, insanın asıl gayesinin Vâcibü'l-Vücûd Zât’a benzemek olduğunu iddia eden, kendini beğenmişçesine “Vâcibü'l-Vücûd’a benzemeye çalışınız.” diyen kaidesi nerede? Evet, insanın sınırsız acz, zaaf, fakr ve ihtiyaçla yoğrulmuş mahiyeti nerede; sonsuz kudret, kuvvet ve zenginlik sahibi, hiçbir şeye muhtaç olmayan Vâcibü'l-Vücûd nerede?..

**
İkinci Misal: Peygamberlerin bildirdiği düsturların toplum hayatındaki neticelerinden veyahut güneş ve aydan tut, bitkileri hayvanların imdadına, hayvanları insanın imdadına, hatta gıdalardaki zerreleri beden hücrelerinin imdadına koşturan yardımlaşma düsturu; cömertlik, ihsan ve ikram kanunu nerede... Felsefenin toplum hayatındaki düsturlarının neticesi olan ve yalnız bir kısım zalim, canavar insanların ve vahşi hayvanların fıtratlarını kötüye kullanmaları yüzünden ortaya çıkan mücadele kanunu nerede? Evet, felsefeciler mücadele kanununu o kadar esaslı ve geniş kabul etmişler ki, “Hayat bir mücadeledir.” diye ahmakça bir hükme varmışlar.

Üçüncü Misal: Peygamberlerin yolunun Allah’ın birliği hakkındaki yüce neticelerinden ve kıymetli düsturlarından “Bir olan şey ancak bir’den meydana gelebilir. Madem her şeyde birlik var, demek eşya bir tek Zât’ın eseridir.” mânâsındaki tevhid düsturu nerede… Eski felsefenin inanca dair olan, “Bir’den ancak bir meydana gelir.” yani, “Bir zâttan, bizzat bir tek şey ortaya çıkabilir. Başka şeyler ise vasıtalar yoluyla ondan vücuda gelir.” diyen, sınırsız zenginlik ve mutlak kudret sahibi Cenâb-ı Hakk’ı aciz vasıtalara muhtaç göstererek bütün sebeplere ve vasıtalara O’nun rubûbiyetinde bir tür ortaklık veren, Hâlık-ı Zülcelâl’e “akl-ı evvel” diye bir sıfatı isnat edip âdeta O’nun mülkünü sebep ve vasıtalara bölüştürerek büyük bir şirke yol açan, inkâra ve dalâlete bulaşmış kanunu nerede? Felsefecilerin yüksek tabakası olan İşrâkiler böyle yaparsa, maddeciler ve tabiatçılar gibi aşağı tabakaların ne halt edeceklerini kıyaslayabilirsin…

**
Dördüncü Misal: Peygamber yolunun hikmetli düsturlarından sırrıyla: “Her şeyin, her canlının kendine ait neticesi ve hikmeti bir ise, Yaratıcısına ait neticeleri ve O’na bakan hikmetleri binlercedir. Her bir şeyin, mesela bir meyvenin, ağacın bütün meyveleri kadar hikmet ve neticeleri bulunur.” büyük hakikatini bildiren hikmet düsturu nerede… Felsefenin, “Her bir canlının mânâsı, neticesi sadece kendine bakar veyahut insanın menfaatleriyle ilgilidir.” diyen, dağ gibi koca bir ağaca hardal tanesi kadar bir meyve, bir netice takılması misali gayet mânâsız, gayesizlik içinde gördüğü hikmetsiz, aldatıcı düsturları nerede? 

İşte felsefenin şu çürük esasları ve vahim neticeleri yüzünden, İslam filozoflarından İbni Sina ve Farabî gibi dâhiler, görünüşteki şaşaasına aldanarak o yola girdiklerinden basit bir mümin derecesini ancak kazanabilmişlerdir. Hatta İmam Gazalî gibi bir “Hüccetü'l İslam” onlara bu dereceyi bile vermemiştir. Hem kelâm ilminin derin âlimlerinden olan Mutezile imamları, gösterişine aldanıp o yola ciddi temas ederek aklı hâkim kabul ettiklerinden ancak günahkâr ve bid’atçı birer mümin derecesine çıkabilmişlerdir. Müslüman ediplerin meşhurlarından, karamsarlığıyla bilinen Ebu’l Alâ el-Maarrî ve yetimane ağlayışıyla şöhret bulan Ömer Hayyam gibiler ise o yolun nefs-i emmareyi okşayan zevkine kapılmaları sebebiyle hakikat ve kemâl ehlince hor görülüp küfürle itham edilmiş, “Edepsizlik yapıyorsunuz, dinden çıkıyorsunuz, dinsizler yetiştiriyorsunuz.” diye men ve ikaz tokatları yemişlerdir.

**
Felsefecilerin yolunun çürük esaslarından biri de şudur: Benlik, zâtında hava gibi zayıf bir mahiyete sahip olduğu halde, kendine felsefenin uğursuz nazarıyla, mânâ-yı ismî yönüyle baktığı için âdeta buhar gibiyken yoğunlaşıp sıvı hale gelir, sonra da ülfet yüzünden ve maddiyatla meşgul olması sebebiyle sanki katılaşır. Ardından gaflet ve inkâr ile iyice donar. Sonra isyan ile bulanıp şeffaflığını kaybeder. Daha sonra o benlik gittikçe kalınlaşıp sahibini yutar. Bütün insanlığın fikirleriyle şişer. Ve nihayet başka insanları, hatta sebepleri kendisiyle kıyaslayıp onlara –kabul etmedikleri ve uzaklaştıkları halde– birer firavunluk verir. İşte o vakit, Hâlık-ı Zülcelâl’in emirlerine karşı isyan vaziyeti alır. Meydan okur gibi Kadîr-i Mutlak’ı acizlikle itham eder. Hatta Yüce Hâlık’ın vasıflarına karışır; işine gelmeyenleri ve nefs-i emmarenin firavunluğunun hoşuna gitmeyenleri ret, inkâr veyahut tahrif eder.

EK: ENE VE HİKMETİ

Tuesday, March 5, 2019

"Choice is the bane of modern life"


By Giles Fraser
 
“Black Americano, please.” A simple enough request to a barrista. But, oh, its not. I’m already grumpy. It’s too early for chat. But the questions keep coming. “Small, medium or large?” she replies. “Medium please” I grunt, hoping that will be the end of the matter. “Drink in or take away?” I reply. “Would you like milk with that?” I resist the temptation to refer my chirpy interrogator back to the original request for a black coffee. “No, thank you.”
Surely that’s enough information. But, no. “Would you like to try our new Guatemalan blend?” I decline, signalling growing irritation. “Would you like a pastry with that…” A list of various croissants and muffins follows. My mood darkens further. All I want is a bloody coffee.

Choice is the bane of modern life. “Existence preceeds essence”, preached the existentialists. What they meant was that who we are is not given at birth, but is constructed by the series of choices we make about who we want to be. “Become who you are”, said Nietzsche some decades before.

From this perspective, life is a never ending succession of choices, a constant work-in-progress of self-definition. We are the authors of our own identity. Mini gods of self-creation. Sartre liked to sit in coffee houses, musing on the meaning of life. But surely even he could not have reckoned with the ubiquity of choice in a consumerist society. I fancy that he, too, would have been broken by the ever-present demand to decide for oneself. As I sip my coffee, a semblance of calm begins to return. Existentialism is too heavy a burden. No more questions, please. I can’t take it any more. I don’t want to be endlessly responsible for me. I want someone else to shoulder the burden on my behalf.

Source: Unherd

Friday, December 14, 2018

Batı'da Entellektüel Kalmadı

Bir durum tespiti olarak şu hususun altını çizmekte yarar var: Batı’da entelektüel kalmadı; dünya yeni bir döneme adım atarken geçmiştekine benzer “kurucu zihin” ortaya çıkmıyor, kurucu zihinlerin mirası üzerinden gidenler de yavaş yavaş tarih sahnesinden çekiliyor. Şu anda Batı düşünce hayatına siyasetine, maddi ve iktisadi evrenine yön verenler, sosyal bilimciler, politikacılar, uzmanlar ve stratejistlerdir. Fonksiyonel değerleri inkar edilmese de, bu zümre içinde yer alanlar entelektüel sıfatını almaya hak kazanmazlar.
Teknoloji, ekonomi, strateji ve politika, yeryüzü ölçeğinde hayatı giderek yoksullaştırmakta, acımasızlaştırmaktadır. Sosyal bilimcilerden filozof veya yüksek düzeyde fikir adamı çıkmaz; sosyal bilimlerin suyunun derinliği bir karışlıktır, bilimlerin sularında sadece ayaklarınızı ıslatırsınız. Entelektüel, okyanusun derin sularına dalar, derinliklerde hikmet incileri arar. Söz konusu dört düzeyde -teknoloji, ekonomi, strateji ve politika- tabiat tüketiliyor, istifçilik gelişiyor, bedenin organizmaya ait istekleri öne çıkıyor. Tabii bunun arkasından da pragmatizmin ve başarı tutkusunun tetiklediği, hegemonik bir kültür yeryüzününün genelini istila ediyor.
Zamanımızda sanat, edebiyat ve felsefe alanında inanılmaz bir zaaf söz konusu. Kurtarıcı paradigmayı inşa etme gücünde olan din, deizm ve nihilizmle atbaşı giden sekülerleşmenin etkisinde özelleşiyor, marjinalleşiyor ve izafi alana çekilmek zorunda bırakılıyor. Din adına hüküm süren iktidarlar dini sekülerleştiriyor. Bu sebepten sürecin anavatanı Batı olduğundan entelektüel çıkmıyor. İyi bir entelektüel ancak dinin evreninde mümkün hayat bulabilir. Hıristiyanlık, Yahudilik, Budizm de entelektüel çıkarabilir, fakat en iyi ve en kâmil anlamdaki entelektüel örnekler sadece İslam’a özeldir ve bu manada sadece İslam entelektüel çıkarabilir. Şu var ki, sahih entelektüel geçmişte olduğu gibi bugün de “zenginlerin (ulusal ve küresel kapitalistlerin) sofrasından ve sultanın sarayından uzak” sade, mütevazi ve çileli bir hayat tarzını seçmeyi göze almalı.
Ali Bulaç, alibulac.net

Saturday, December 9, 2017

Numeracy, Quantity and Logarithmic Scale


(Original article by Philip Ball, aeon.co)

Why can we count to 152? OK, most of us don’t need to stop there, but that’s my point. Counting to 152, and far beyond, comes to us so naturally that it’s hard not to regard our ability to navigate indefinitely up the number line as something innate, hard-wired into us.

Scientists have long claimed that our ability with numbers is indeed biologically evolved – that we can count because counting was a useful thing for our brains to be able to do. The hunter-gatherer who could tell which herd or flock of prey was the biggest, or which tree held the most fruit, had a survival advantage over the one who couldn’t. What’s more, other animals show a rudimentary capacity to distinguish differing small quantities of things: two bananas from three, say. Surely it stands to reason, then, that numeracy is adaptive.

But is it really? Being able to tell two things from three is useful, but being able to distinguish 152 from 153 must have been rather less urgent for our ancestors. More than about 100 sheep was too many for one shepherd to manage anyway in the ancient world, never mind millions or billions.

The cognitive scientist Rafael Núñez of the University of California at San Diego doesn’t buy the conventional wisdom that ‘number’ is a deep, evolved capacity. He thinks that it is a product of culture, like writing and architecture.

**
Numerical ability is more than a matter of being able to distinguish two objects from three, even if it depends on that ability. No non-human animal has yet been found able to distinguish 152 items from 153. Chimps can’t do that, no matter how hard you train them, yet many children can tell you even by the age of five that the two numbers differ in the same way as do the equally abstract numbers 2 and 3: namely, by 1.

What seems innate and shared between humans and other animals is not this sense that the differences between 2 and 3 and between 152 and 153 are equivalent (a notion central to the concept of number) but, rather, a distinction based on relative difference, which relates to the ratio of the two quantities. It seems we never lose that instinctive basis of comparison.

**
According to Núñez, is that the brain’s natural capacity relates not to number but to the cruder concept of quantity. ‘A chick discriminating a visual stimulus that has what (some) humans designate as “one dot” from another one with “three dots” is a biologically endowed behaviour that involves quantity but not number,’ he said. ‘It does not need symbols, language and culture.’

**
Although researchers often assume that numerical cognition is inherent to humans, Núñez points out that not all cultures show it. Plenty of pre-literate cultures that have no tradition of writing or institutional education, including indigenous societies in Australia, South America and Africa, lack specific words for numbers larger than about five or six. Bigger numbers are instead referred to by generic words equivalent to ‘several’ or ‘many’. Such cultures ‘have the capacity to discriminate quantity, but it is rough and not exact, unlike numbers’, said Núñez.

That lack of specificity doesn’t mean that quantity is no longer meaningfully distinguished beyond the limit of specific number words, however. If two children have ‘many’ oranges but the girl evidently has lots more than the boy, the girl might be said to have, in effect, ‘many many’ or ‘really many’. In the language of the Munduruku people of the Amazon, for example, adesu indicates ‘several’ whereas ade implies ‘really lots’. These cultures live with what to us looks like imprecision: it really doesn’t matter if, when the oranges are divided up, one person gets 152 and the other 153. And frankly, if we aren’t so number-fixated, it really doesn’t matter. So why bother having words to distinguish them?

Some researchers have argued that the default way that humans quantify things is not arithmetically – one more, then another one – but logarithmically. The logarithmic scale is stretched out for small numbers and compressed for larger ones, so that the difference between two things and three can appear as significant as the difference between 200 and 300 of them.

**
In 2008, the cognitive neuroscientist Stanislas Dehaene of the Collège de France in Paris and his coworkers reported evidence that the Munduruku system of accounting for quantities corresponds to a logarithmic division of the number line. In computerised tests, they presented a tribal group of 33 Munduruku adults and children with a diagram analogous to the number line commonly used to teach primary-school children, albeit without any actual number markings along it. The line had just one circle at one end and 10 circles at the other. The subjects were asked to indicate where on the line groupings of up to 10 circles should be placed.

Whereas Western adults and children will generally indicate evenly spaced (arithmetically distributed) numbers, the Munduruku people tended to choose a gradually decreasing spacing as the numbers of circles got larger, roughly consistent with that found for abstract numbers on a logarithmic scale. Dehaene and colleagues think that for children to learn to space numbers arithmetically, they have to overcome their innately logarithmic intuitions about quantity.

Attributing more weight to the difference between small than between large numbers makes good sense in the real world, and fits with what Fias says about judging by difference ratios. A difference between families of two and three people is of comparable significance in a household as a difference between 200 and 300 people is in a tribe, while the distinction between tribes of 152 and 153 is negligible.

It’s easy to read this as a ‘primitive’ way of reasoning, but anthropology has long dispelled such patronising prejudice. After all, some cultures with few number words might make much more fine-grained linguistic distinctions than we do for, say, smells or family hierarchies. You develop words and concepts for what truly matters to your society. From a practical perspective, one could argue that it’s actually the somewhat homogeneous group of industrialised cultures that look odd, with their pedantic distinction between 1,000,002 and 1,000,003.

Whether the Munduruku really map quantities onto a quasi-logarithmic division of ‘number space’ is not clear, however. That’s a rather precise way of describing a broad tendency to make more of small-number distinctions than of large-number ones. Núñez is skeptical of Dehaene’s claim that all humans conceptualise an abstract number line at all. He says that the variability of where Munduruku people (especially the uneducated adults, who are the most relevant group for questions of innateness versus culture) placed small quantities on the number line was too great to support the conclusion about how they thought of number placement. Some test subjects didn’t even consistently rank the progressive order of the equivalents of 1, 2 and 3 on the lines they were given.

‘Some individuals tended to place the numbers at the extremes of the line segment, disregarding the distance between them,’ said Núñez. ‘This violates basic principles of how the mapping of the number line works at all, regardless of whether it is logarithmic or arithmetic.’

Building on the clues from anthropology, neuroscience can tell us additional details about the origin of quantity discrimination. Brain-imaging studies have revealed a region of the infant brain involved in this task – distinguishing two dots from three, say. This ability truly does seem to be innate, and researchers who argue for a biological basis of number have claimed that children recruit these neural resources when they start to learn their culture’s symbolic system of numbers. Even though no one can distinguish 152 from 153 randomly spaced dots visually (that is, without counting), the argument is that the basic cognitive apparatus for doing so is the same as that used to tell 2 from 3.

But that appealing story doesn’t accord with the latest evidence, according to Ansari. ‘Surprisingly, when you look deeply at the patterns of brain activation, we and others found quite a lot of evidence to suggest a large amount of dissimilarity between the way our brains process non-symbolic numbers, like arrays of dots, and symbolic numbers,’ he said. ‘They don’t seem to be correlated with one another. That challenges the notion that the brain mechanisms for processing culturally invented number symbols maps on to the non-symbolic number system. I think these systems are not as closely related as we thought.’

If anything, the evidence now seems to suggest that the cause-and-effect relationship works the other way: ‘When you learn symbols, you start to do these dot-discrimination tasks differently.’

This picture makes intuitive sense, Ansari argues, when you consider how hard kids have to work to grasp numbers as opposed to quantities. ‘One thing I’ve always struggled with is that on the one hand we have evidence that infants can discriminate quantity, but on the other hand it takes children between two to three years to learn the relationship between number words and quantities,’ he said. ‘If we thought there was a very strong innate basis on to which you just map the symbolic system, why should there be such a protracted developmental trajectory, and so much practice and explicit instruction necessary for that?’

But the apparent disconnect between the two types of symbolic thought raises a mystery of its own: how do we grasp number at all if we have only the cognitive machinery for the cruder notion of quantity? That conundrum is one reason why some researchers can’t accept Núñez’s claim that the concept of number is a cultural trait, even if it draws on innate dispositions. ‘The brain, a biological organ with a genetically defined wiring scheme, is predisposed to acquire a number system,’ said the neurobiologist Andreas Nieder of the University of Tübingen in Germany. ‘Culture can only shape our number faculty within the limits of the capacities of the brain. Without this predisposition, number symbols would lie [forever] beyond our grasp.’

‘This is for me the biggest challenge in the field: where do the meanings for number symbols come from?’ Ansari asks. ‘I really think that a fuzzy system for large quantities is not going to be the best hunting ground for a solution.’

Perhaps what we draw on, he thinks, is not a simple symbol-to-quantity mapping, but a sense of the relationships between numbers – in other words, a notion of arithmetical rules rather than just a sense of cardinal (number-line) ordering. ‘Even when children understand the cardinality principle – a mapping of number symbols to quantities – they don’t necessarily understand that if you add one more, you get to the next highest number,’ Ansari said. ‘Getting the idea of number off the ground turns out to be extremely complex, and we’re still scratching the surface in our understanding of how this works.’

The debate over the origin of our number sense might itself seem rather abstract, but it has tangible practical consequences. Most notably, beliefs about the relative roles of biology and culture can influence attitudes toward mathematical education.

The nativist view that number sense is biological seemed to be supported by a 2008 study by researchers at the Johns Hopkins University in Baltimore, which showed 14-year-old test subjects’ ability to discriminate at a glance between exact numerical quantities (such as the number of dots in an image) correlated with their mathematics test scores going back to kindergarten. In other words, if you’re inherently good at assessing numbers visually, you’ll be good at maths. The findings were used to develop educational tools such as Panamath to assess and improve mathematical ability.

via Aeon

Non-Western Philosophies


One of the major Western philosophers who read with fascination Jesuit accounts of Chinese philosophy was Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716). He was stunned by the apparent correspondence between binary arithmetic (which he invented, and which became the mathematical basis for all computers) and the I Ching, or Book of Changes, the Chinese classic that symbolically represents the structure of the Universe via sets of broken and unbroken lines, essentially 0s and 1s. (In the 20th century, the psychoanalyst Carl Jung was so impressed with the I Ching that he wrote a philosophical foreword to a translation of it.) Leibniz also said that, while the West has the advantage of having received Christian revelation, and is superior to China in the natural sciences, ‘certainly they surpass us (though it is almost shameful to confess this) in practical philosophy, that is, in the precepts of ethics and politics adapted to the present life and the use of mortals’.

via Aeon

Saturday, September 23, 2017

The Loophole in the Hedonic Treadmill



When Fyodor Dostoyevsky wrote, in The House of the Dead, that “Man is a creature that can get accustomed to anything,” he was talking about the cruelties and deprivations of life in Siberian prison camp. But the human tendency to adapt or “get accustomed” to situations is more profound than even Dostoyevsky may have realized.
Imagine a person who, after years of drinking bland, watery beer from a mass-market brewery, finally tastes a really good craft beer. At first she notices the intensity of the flavor. A few more sips and she comes to appreciate the beer’s complexity and the exquisite balance between bitterness and sweetness. The craft beer is so much more flavorful than what she has been used to drinking, and the experience is highly enjoyable. But check in after a few months when she has been drinking the craft beer on a regular basis. Something has changed. The experience is no longer as special as it was at first. It now takes an even greater taste sensation to yield the same thrill our beer drinker experienced the first few times she tried the craft beer.
We adapt. A great pleasure, repeated often enough, becomes routine, and it takes an even greater treat to give us the same enjoyment. When we get used to having more, it takes more to please us. (Conversely, when we get used to having less, it takes less to please us.) This is the known as the “hedonic treadmill.” It’s analogous to the well-known tendency to adapt to physical stress. When you first start lifting weights, for example, a relatively light weight might be all it takes to start putting on muscle. But once the body adapts to that exercise, heavier and heavier weights will be needed to keep getting stronger.
The idea of the hedonic treadmill can apply to discrete pleasures—like getting accustomed to better beer—or it can apply to an overall lifestyle. There is evidence that if an individual’s basic needs are met, after a certain point, increases in income do not lead to much greater happiness. As the money we have to spend goes up, so too do our expectations and desires—and with them the possibility of disappointment. A now-classic study from 1978 compared the happiness of lottery winners with a control group drawn from the same neighborhoods. The researchers interviewed lottery winners after the initial thrill had worn off. When asked to rate their present level of happiness, the lottery winners answered in the same way as did the control group. The two groups also made similar predictions about their future happiness. And when asked about a number of mundane pleasures—talking with a friend or eating breakfast—the lottery winners actually derived less pleasure than did the control group.
Maybe those lottery winners weren’t more happy because they spent their winnings on the wrong things. 2011 survey of the available empirical research indicates that spending money on experiences (for example, vacations, dance classes, or nights out with friends) makes people more happy than does spending money on material goods. One of the reasons is that, while we quickly adapt to that new handbag or pair of shoes, a good experience provides a happy memory that can be revisited again and again, with less threat of adaptation.
JEANETTE BICKNELL, Nautilus

Also check: Hedonic Treadmill